Buradasınız

KLASİK İLE ‘YÜCE’ ARASINDA PİRANESİ

PIRANESI BETWEEN CLASSICAL AND SUBLIME

Journal Name:

Publication Year:

Abstract (2. Language): 
The eighteenth century saw an increasing number of debates and polemics in aesthetical theory. One of these concerned the difference between the beautiful and the sublime, which influenced especially philosophical approaches to art and design in poetry, music, painting, as well as in architecture (2). Two philosophers contributing to the discussion, Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) and Edmund Burke (1729-1797), held diverse views on the concepts of the beautiful and the sublime: while agreeing that they were essential to appreciating human creativity, the philosophers sustained rather opposite positions concerning their respective origins and whether or not they were inherent to human nature. Moreover, architects and artists utilized the notions of beautiful and sublime in their work both conceptually in their writings and visually in design. In this lively environment flourishing around the two concepts, Giovanni Battista Piranesi (1720-1778) etched in 1765 the fragment of a statement on the sublime by Julien-David Le Roy (1724-1803). The fragment came from Le Roy’s 1758 Les Ruines des plus beaux monuments de la Grèce and Piranesi placed the words on the inscription plate at the center of the façade, directly above the entrance of the building he was depicting. The etching was published in Plate VIII of his dialogue Parere su l’architetture (Figure 1): “Pour ne pas faire de cet art sublime un vil métier où l’on ne feroit que copier sans choix”: ‘In order not to render this sublime art a vile craft where one would only copy without discretion’ (Parere, 139, 152-153 n.139). The wider context of Le Roy’s words in Les Ruines des plus beaux monuments de la Grèce had called for discretion on the architect’s part in situating himself between blind compliance with classical norm and ‘accepting no rules whatsoever’ (“n’addmettre aucunes règles”) in the design of monuments (Le Roy, 1758, 1). Le Roy had further warned that, A fair appreciation of these principles should help us avoid two very dangerous improprieties in architecture: that of accepting no rules whatsoever and taking caprice as the only guide in the composition of PIRANESI BETWEEN CLASSICAL AND SUBLIME (1) Fatma İpek EK and Deniz ŞENGEL Received: 08.06.2006; Final Text: 18.05.2007 Keywords: Giovanni Battista Piranesi; Immanuel Kant; Edmund Burke; Roman architecture, eighteenth-century aesthetical discussions; beautiful; sublime. 1. An early version of this article comprises Chapter 6 of the master thesis “The Archaeological Sublime: History and Architecture in Piranesi’s Drawings,” presented to the İzmir Institute of Technology (Ek, 2006). This article was made possible by a Scientific Research Grant from the Institute, 2005 İYTE 11. 2. For an overview of the emergence of the concepts of the sublime and beautiful, identified as ‘picturesque’, in the British context, see Mallgrave, 2005, 51-55.Monuments; and that of accepting too many [rules]; constraining thereby Architects’ imagination and making of this sublime Art a species of craft in which each only copies, without discretion, that which has been done by some ancient Architects (1758, 1). Le Roy was using the term sublime to describe the architecture of monuments. Piranesi had used Le Roy’s statement as the central inscription of precisely a monument, identifying sublime architecture with architecture of monuments (Figure 2). Piranesi had changed by one word Le Roy’s statement in order to render it more emphatic, substituting “un vil métier” (a vile craft) for Le Roy’s more neutral “un espèce de métier” (a species of craft). Le Roy too, however, had conceived of dogged compliance with classical norm as something lowly -a kind of ‘craft’ rather than Art. Both Piranesi and Le Roy were obviously within the bounds of eighteenthcentury European culture in their view of a hierarchic distinction between art (art) and craft (métier) (3). While the profession of architecture had since Vitruvius been considered to be equally art and craft (De arch. Book I: II-III C), the eighteenth century was increasingly separating the two domains and establishing a hierarchical relationship between them in which art superseded craft. The result was discussion in architectural environments as to the implications of this new division for the discipline. Le Roy, as we saw, was alerting his reader that the artist-architect could commit faults that would degrade the work into craft. Piranesi’s paraphrase of Le Roy with vil métier went further and described craft as ‘vile’ or ‘lowly’, identified mimetic architecture with craft, and made the difference between sublime architecture and classical imitation even more trenchant. By identifying architecture of monuments with a particular, elevated style, however, both Piranesi and Le Roy participated in a hierarchic genre theory that remained Aristotelian and thus, classical.The eighteenth-century debate on the beautiful and sublime concerned architecture in a particular way: it engaged the distinction between ‘beautiful architecture’ and ‘sublime architecture’ with a view on the degree of presence of classical rules as opposed to freedom from these rules and identified their difference as the gap between ‘Art’ and ‘craft’. Refraining from entering into a discussion of the art/craft distinction as this has been excellently conducted elsewhere (4), this article investigates Piranesi’s drawings of sublime architecture against the background of the contemporary philosophical debate on the beautiful and sublime, and situates the eighteenth-century notion of sublime architecture in terms of the culture’s revisionary, but ambiguous, attitude to classicism. The example of Piranesi should prove particularly significant in the said context as this prolific architect of the sublime was at once firmly rooted in classicism as, among others, Plate VIII of the Parere evinced.
Abstract (Original Language): 
On sekizinci yüzyılda, estetik biliminin olduğu kadar mimarlık tarihinin de doğuşu bağlamında ivme kazanan tartışmalar, mimarlık disiplinini doğal olarak etkilemişti. Estetik tartışmaların temeli mimarilerin tarihsel köken tartışmalarına bağlanıyor ve ‘güzel’ ile ‘yüce’ olmak üzere iki etki üzerine odaklanıyordu: ‘Güzel’i temsil ettiği düşünülen Yunan tarzı, ‘yüce’yle özdeşleştirilen Roma ve Mısır tarzlarının karşısına yerleştirilmekteydi. Giovanni Battista Piranesi (1720-1778) gibi mimar ve düşünürlerin görsel ve yazınsal çalışmalarında söz konusu estetik ve tarihsel savlar takip edilebiliyordu. Piranesi, Roma mimarlık ve uygarlığının kökenini ‘güzel’ Yunan’a dayandıran Winckelmann gibi çağdaşlarının aksine, Roma mimarî estetiğinin ‘yüce’ unsurlar barındırdığını, dolayısıyla Mısır medeniyetinden türediğini savunuyordu. Tüm çizimlerinde antik Roma’nın ‘yüce’ mimarisini resmeden Piranesi, böylece estetik tartışmaların ‘yüce’ cephesinde yerini alıyordu. On sekizinci yüzyılın iki önemli filozofu Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) ile Edmund Burke (1729-1797) estetiğin bileşenleri ‘güzel’ ve ‘yüce’ üzerine çalışmalarıyla tartışmaları hızlandırmıştı. Bu iki kavram on sekizinci yüzyıl felsefe ve tasarım kuramlarını aynı ölçüde etkilemekle birlikte, makale temel olarak Kant ile Burke’ün ‘yüce’ tanımları üzerinden Piranesi’nin görsel ve metinsel çalışmalarının karşılaştırmalı okumasını yapmaktadır. Kant ve Burke’ün ‘yüce’ açıklamalarında küçük ayrılıklar görülmekle birlikte ikisi de temelde aynı şeyi söylemişlerdir. Özellikle Kant’ın Güzellik ve Yücelik Duygusu Üzerine Gözlemler (1764) ve Burke’ün Yücelik ve Güzellik Fikirlerimizin Kaynağı Hakkında Felsefî bir Araştırma (1757) başlıklı çalışmalarındaki ifadeler Piranesi’nin çizimlerinde takip edilebilmektedir. Piranesi, Kant’ın ve Burke’ün anlattığı ‘yüce’yi mimarî çizim diliyle aktarmıştı. Piranesi, on sekizinci yüzyıla egemen olan ‘yüce’ etkiyi Venedikli bir mimarın gözüyle yeniden yorumluyordu.
FULL TEXT (PDF): 
17-34

REFERENCES

References: 

ABRAMS, M.H. (1973) Natural Supernaturalism: Tradition and Revolution
in Romantic Literature, W. W. Norton and Company, New York,
London.
ARISTOTLE (1887; 1995) Ars poetica, The Poetics, trans. W. H. Fyfe (1982)
Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass.; William Heinemann,
London.
ARISTOTLE (1837; 1994) Ars rhetorica, The “Art” of Rhetoric, trans. J. H.
Freese (1926) Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass.; William
Heinemann, London.
AUGUSTYN, J. (2000) Subjectivity in the Fictional Ruin: The Caprice Genre,
Romanic Review (91: 4): 433-57.
BLUNT, A. (1940; 1962) Artistic Theory in Italy 1450-1660, Oxford University
Press, Oxford.
BURKE, E. (1757) On Taste. A Philosophical Inquiry into the Origin of Our Ideas
of The Sublime and Beautiful with several other Additions. Reflections on
the French Revolution. A letter to a Noble Lord, ed. C. W. Eliot (1937) P.
F. Collier and Son Corporation, New York.
CASSIRER, E. (1951; 1979) Die Philosophie der Aufklärung, The Philosophy
of the Enlightenment, trans. F. Kölln and J.P. Pettegrove (1979)
Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ.
COULTER, J.A. (1976) The Literary Microcosm. Theories of Interpretation of the
Later Neoplatonists, E.J. Brill, Leiden.
DIDEROT, D. and D’ALEMBERT, J.R. (1751) Encyclopédie ou dictionnaire
raisonné des sciences, des arts et des métiers, 35 Bde., Paris.
DIELS, H. and KRANZ, W. (1951) Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, 6th ed.,
Weidmann, Berlin.
DU FRESNOY, C.A. (1668; 1773) De Arte graphica, The art of painting, trans.
J. Dryden (1695) Bernard Lintot, London.
EDGERTON, S.Y. (1975) The Renaissance Rediscovery of Linear Perspective,
Harper and Row Publishers, New York, Evanston, San Francisco,
London.EK, F. İ. (2006) The Archaeological Sublime: History and Architecture in
Piranesi’s Drawings, unpublished M.Sc. Dissertation, Department of
Architecture, İzmir Institute of Technology, İzmir.
HAGSTRUM, J. (1958; 1987) The Sister Arts: The Tradition of Literary
Pictorialism and English Poetry from Dryden to Gray, University of
Chicago Press, Chicago.
HENDRIX, J. (2003) Architectural forms and philosophical structures, Peter
Lang, New York.
KANT, I. (1764) Beobachtungen über das Gefühl des Schönen und
Erhabenen, Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime,
trans. F. J. T. Goldthwait (1960) University of California Press,
Berkeley, Los Angeles, London.
KANT, I. (1790) Kritik der Urteilskraft, Critique of Judgement, trans. J. C.
Meredith (1978) Clarendon Press, Oxford.
KNOX, I. (1978) The Aesthetic Theories of Kant, Hegel, and Schopenhauer,
Humanities Press, New Jersey; Harvester Press, Sussex.
KRISTELLER, P.O. (1965) Renaissance Thought and the Arts, Princeton
University Press, Princeton, New Jersey.
LAUGIER, M.A. (1753; 1966) Essai sur l’architecture, Gregg, Farnborough.
LE BRUN, C. (1668) L’expression des passions et autres conférences, The
Expression of the Passions, trans. Julien Philipe (1994) Editions Dédale,
Paris.
LEGRAND, J.G. (1799, 1921) Notice historique sur la vie et sur les ouvrages de
J. B. Piranesi, Architecte, Peintre et Graveur... Redigée sur les notes et les
pieces communiquées par ses fils, les Compagnons et les Continuateurs de
ses nombreux travaux, Bibliothèque Nationale, Paris; G. Morazzoni,
Milan.
LE ROY, J. (1758) Les Ruines des plus beaux monuments de la Grèce, H. L.
Guerin et L. F. Delatour, Paris.
LONGINUS (1694; 1995) Peri Hypsous, On the Sublime, trans. W. H. Fyfe
(1995) Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass.
LUCRETIUS (1656; 1975) De Rerum Natura, On the Nature of Things, trans.
W.H.D. Rouse (1957) Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass.;
William Heinemann, London.
MALLGRAVE, H. F. (2005) Modern Architectural Theory: A Historical Survey,
1673-1968, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, New York.
MURRAY, P.J. (1971) Piranesi and the Grandeur of Ancient Rome, Thames and
Hudson, London.
PALOMINO, A. (1715; 1988) Theórica de la pintura, Lucas Antonio Bedmar,
Madrid.
PENNY, N. (1978) Piranesi, Oresko Books, London; Hippocrene Books,
New York.
PIRANESI, G.B. (1743) Prima Parte di Architetture e Prospettive, n.p., Rome.
PIRANESI, G.B., DUFLOS, F. et al. (1745; 1748) Varie Vedute di Roma Antica
e Moderna, n.p., Rome.
PIRANESI, G.B. (1745) Invenzioni capricci di carceri, n.p., Rome.PIRANESI, G.B. (1756) Le antichità romane, n.p., Rome.
PIRANESI, G.B. (1760) Carceri d’Invenzione, n.p., Rome.
PIRANESI, G.B. (1748-78) Vedute di Roma, n.p., Rome.
PIRANESI, G.B. (1762) Il Campo Marzio dell’antica Roma, n.p., Rome.
PIRANESI, G.B. (1765; 2002) Osservazioni sopra la lettre de Monsieur
Mariette. Parere su l’architettura. Della introduzione e del progresso
delle belle arti in europa ne’tempi antichi, Observations on the Letter of
Monsieur Mariette: With Opinions on Architecture, and a Preface to a New
Treatise on the Introduction and Progress of the Fine Arts in Europe in
Ancient Times, introduction by John Wilton-Ely (2002) Getty Research
Institute for the History of Art and the Humanities, Los Angeles and
California.
PIRANESI, G.B. (1769) Diverse Maniere d’Adornare i Cammini ed Ogni Altra
Parte Degli Edifizi Desunte dall’Architettura Egizia, Etrusca, e Greca, Con
un Ragionamento Apologetico in Difesa dell’Architettura Egizia e Toscana,
n.p., Rome.
RAPIN, R. (1701; 1709) Du grand ou du sublime dans les moeurs et dans les
différentes conditions des hommes, OEuvres, Volume III, Pierre Mortier,
Amsterdam.
RYKWERT, J. (1993) On Adam’s House in Paradise, The Idea of the Primitive
Hut in Architectural History, MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass. and
London.
RYKWERT, J. (1980) The First Moderns: The Architects of the Eighteenth
Century, MIT Press Cambridge, Mass. and London.
SAINTSBURY, G. (1902) A History of Criticism and Literary Taste in Europe,
William Blackwood and Sons, New York.
TAYLOR, C.C.W. (1999) The Atomists: Leucippus and Democritus. Fragments,
A Text and Translation with Commentary, Toronto.
THEBERT, Y. (1987) The Domestic Architecture of the Ruling Class, A
History of Private Life from Pagan Rome to Byzantium, ed. Paul Veyne
(1985), Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass. and London;
325-352.
VASI, G. (1747) Magnificenze di Roma Antica e Moderna, n.p., Rome.
VIRGIL (1892; 1993) Aeneis, The Aeneid, trans. John Dryden (1697) Folio
Society, London.
VITRUVIUS (1914) De architectura libri decem, The Ten Books on
Architecture, trans. Morris Hicky Morgan (1960) Dover Publications,
New York.
WENDORF, R. (2001) Piranesi’s Double Ruin, Eighteenth-Century Studies
(34:2) 161-180.
WILTON-ELY, J. (1993) Piranesi as Architect and Designer, Pierpont Morgan
Library, New York; Yale University Press, New Haven and London.
WILTON-ELY, J. (1978) The Mind and Art of Giovanni Battista Piranesi,
Thames and Hudson, London.
WINCKELMANN, J.J. (1764; 1880) Geschichte der Kunst des Alterthums, The
History of Ancient Art, trans. G. H. Lodge, Osgood, Boston.WINCKELMANN, J.J. (1755; 1765; 1992) Gedanken über die Nachahmung
der Griechischen Werke in der Mahlerey und Bildbauer-Kunst,
Thoughts on the Imitation of Greek Works in Painting and Sculpture, ed.
Michele Cometa (1992) Aesthetica edizioni, Palermo.
WORDSWORTH, W. (1787-1849) Letter to J. Fletcher, Letters of the
Wordsworth Family, Volume II, ed. W. Knight (1907).

Thank you for copying data from http://www.arastirmax.com